Search This Blog

Thursday 25 May 2017

Persistence and Personal Identity

On Persistence and the Problem of Temporary Intrinsics and how this bears on Personal Identity

‘Most people think that they have a ‘self’ that persists over long stretches of time, through significant psychological (and physical) changes. Is this belief justifiable?’

The answer to the question is ‘No, it is a religious commitment, in the sense that it is a belief that makes no sense when logically analysed which nevertheless plays a massive role in our lives, society and culture’. This response may seem overly tendentious, but I see it as unavoidable.[1] In A Treatise of Human Nature, David Hume discusses the question of personal identity in a broader defence of an error theory about identity of macroscopic particulars over time. I submit that Hume’s fairly short discussion of these issues in this book is better than that of leading late-20th Century four-dimensionalist metaphysicians like W.V.O Quine, David Lewis and Theodore Sider (and better from a four-dimensionalist’s perspective). I believe this because I think Hume fully embraces the view that the way we commonly think and talk about individuals or particulars in the world is not based on an accurate understanding of reality, which I believe to be true. In this essay, I will argue that Hume is right that there are no concrete entities in our (speaking loosely) Heraclitean world which persist numerically identically through time[2]; that Hume is right to see humans or other living creatures as, as far as persistence is concerned, not very metaphysically different from other living (and even non-living) macroscopic objects; that he is right that we “confound […] “numerical and specific identity [qualitative identity or close resemblance] […] and in our thinking and reasoning employ one for the other” [Hume, 1736: Book II, Section VI]; and that he is right to position himself as a relativist or normativist about accounts of personal identity, a position which opens up the conceptual possibility for attempting to adopt a different – perhaps morally and emotionally superior [Parfit, 1984; Schopenhauer 1818-19] – religious commitment than the conventional ‘endurantist’-type religious commitment.

I’ll begin this essay by trying my best to briefly stake out the neologistic vocabulary that I have decided to use to try to express my Humean position on ‘identity of objects over time’ (a position whose popularity obviously isn’t helped by the fact that it’s very hard to think about and articulate). I think that the language we use to talk about (at least) macroscopic particulars/individuals – i.e. objects or things which are concrete, living or not, i.e. not species or types – is metaphysically in error, because we talk as if there don’t just solidly exist instant-instances (instance-time slices) of species or sorts, but as if there solidly exist properly persistent instances of sorts (“the [extended-through-time] cow”, “the apple”, “the tree”, “that shoe”) – which is false.[3] But saying that this is false raises a universe of problems. Further disambiguation becomes overwhelmingly difficult, because we are bogged down in a language which in its fundamental conceptual structure contradicts what we are trying to convey.
One thing I can happily say that we can ascribe properties to instant-instances of sorts. But I certainly do not want to say that we have to radically rethink the nature of sorts themselves so that they become merely abstract groupings of intrinsically similar instant-instances; making this kind of revision would be very undesirable. The more important point is that it would be unnecessary: we can accept that the ontology we use in everyday language, as well as in the biological and social sciences (and the chemical sciences too, but I want to stick to the ‘macroscopic’) is not God’s ontology (let ‘representationalism’, as Huw Price [2013] uses the term, be damned), because, whilst sorts may or may not be as real or more fundamental than instant-instances (Platonism versus nominalism is still perfectly alive), there is no question that persistent individuals do not exist as fundamentally as instant-instances – and yet all of our sorts collect together these imaginary entities. (It would still be a useful and important project to attempt to give an account of how you can save a non-extreme-reductionist ontology while accepting that there do not exist persistent individuals, but this is a short essay; one crutch is that a proponent of my position can still talk about evolution patterns of instant-instances with similar intrinsics, and therefore avoid weird conclusions like that early embryos of mammals should all be grouped together because they’re all intrinsically very similar when they’re early embryos (ignoring DNA differences).)
Onto the argument.
In Section IV Part VI of A Treatise of Human Nature, “Of Personal Identity”, Hume points out some childishly simple empirical facts about the way living humans undergo change:
“Our eyes cannot turn in their sockets without varying our perceptions. Our thought is still more variable than our sight; and all our other senses and faculties contribute to this change; nor is there any single power of the soul, which remains unalterably the same, perhaps for one moment.” [Hume, 1894/1736: 134].
These suffice to show that the notion of “some philosophers” that for each person there exists one entity called a “Self” of “perfect identity and simplicity” has no basis in reality, and thus that there is not really such a thing (in exactly the same sense that there is not really such a thing as ghosts) [133].
Like me, Hume doesn’t think that humans are metaphysically special in terms of persistence, and it is therefore natural that after observing that the endurantist notion of the Self has no basis in reality, he quickly moves onto a deeper discussion of how our untutored thoughts about the persistence of “animals and plants” (and even non-living macroscopic ‘things’, one notices) lead us to an “absurdity”.
As he explains, “Our propension to confound identity with relation is so great, that we are apt to imagine something unknown and mysterious, connecting the parts, beside their relation.” [135]. 
For those who are concerned about such things, he also observes correctly that “the controversy concerning identity is not merely a dispute of words” because “when we attribute identity, in an improper sense [the numerical sense], to variable or interrupted objects [collections of causally related object-instances which become increasingly different with distance across the 4-d block], our mistake is not confin’d to the expression, but is commonly attended with a fiction, either of something invariable and uninterrupted, or of something mysterious and inexplicable.” [135].
As Hume’s words imply, the burden of proof lies on the mystic or lunatic who claims there is numerical identity between instance-instants with different properties, not on the person who points out that there is unambiguously not (or that you don’t really mean numerical identity).

A natural response by a perdurantist or stage theorist to this would be to protest that I’m ‘copping out’ of actually giving my own account of persistence or personal identity, and with no overwhelmingly compelling reason to do so: after all, my radical Humean empiricism has massive costs in severing too violently the connection between language and reality, in the process laying waste to canonical theories of reference and also popular Quinean notions about ontological commitment. However, the truth is that Lewis’ perdurantism and Theodore Sider’s stage theory are pointless, since they don’t actually give an account of our concept of personal identity, but something completely different (for no reason, since they’re also not descriptions of anything in reality).[4] As David Braddon-Mitchell has suggested [real-life], in the ordinary speech of human time-slices, sometimes the time-slices (if we’re talking about big enough time-slices that there is ‘room’ to utter a sentence) use the word “I” to mean the nearby time-slices which will soon emerge from them (“I really want to get drunk”) – a kind of usage for which the stage theory sort of ‘accounts’ – and yet human time-slices often also think of themselves as collections of lots of the time-slices to which they are causally connected, even though these time-slices are very different (“I’ve had a good life”, “She’s a good person”), a usage which very roughly aligns with the perdurantist account of persons as four-dimensional ‘worms’. I say the latter only very roughly aligns with the perdurantist account of persons because, in truth, the perdurantist account of persons doesn’t nicely line up with any part of our everyday talk. Four-dimensional worms are not agents who perform actions, nor do they have responsibilities, nor do they speak or act or think, nor do they have memories, and so on.
The non-perdurantist David Wiggins makes a similar kind of argument against perdurantism, in slightly more high-falutin’ language: “Anything that is part of a Lesniewskian sum [a mereological whole defined by its parts] is necessarily part of it…But no person or normal material object is necessarily in the total state that will correspond to the person- or object-moment postulated by the theory under discussion” [1980: 168]. This is a way of saying that the ‘4-D worm persons’ have very different modal properties from persons as we naturally think of them. We want to say that “I might have done this” or “I might have been this” but if what “I” is is really a worm all of whose temporal parts are necessary components, then one is forced to turn to the analysis of such sentences that Lewis himself turned to: “there is a world in which a counterpart of mine might have done this”. [Lewis, 1971: 205]
This is clearly not intuitive!

After Hume has finished pointing out that that our fundamental way of breaking up the world as a set of environments populated by individuals which persist over time has no reality, he makes a strong relativist claim about the nature of philosophical disputes about what It takes for “survival” or continuity of the “Self”: “As the relations, and the easiness of the transition may diminish by insensible degrees, we have no just standard, by which we can decide any dispute concerning the time, when they acquire or lose a title to the name of identity.” [139]. This claim falls straight out of accepting the Humean view of the unreality of persistence. There is good reason to think that the psychological continuity-and-connectedness account of personal ‘identity’ is, overall, a better account of what we typically think it takes for survival than the physical continuity account [Nichols S & Bruno M, 2010], but no reason to say one is True: they’re both just ways of thinking about what people generally think matters about our existence.
As this human instance-instant suggested in the introduction, this human instance-instant thinks it’s more liberating and morally desirable (and ‘in tune with reality’ in at least a weak sense) to try to jettison attachment to the idea that there is a fixed “you” and to instead focus more on being ‘at one’ with sentient life. Many mystics and philosophers have held this kind of view, as is well-known. Arthur Schopenhauer in The World as Will and Representation advocated that we are all tiny parts of the great universal force-of-striving known as “the Will”, and that to achieve tranquillity, enlightenment, freedom and pure knowledge (self-consciously analogous for Schopenhauer to Buddhist nirvana) we must engage in a heroic struggle to try to become at one with the universal Will against our own will-to-live, manifest in our base and animalistic instincts and impulses. Such a philosophy led him to write many magnificent passages like the following:
 “This freeing of [“pure, will-less”] knowledge lifts us as wholly and entirely away from [the individual will], as do sleep and dreams; happiness and unhappiness have disappeared; we are no longer individual; the individual is forgotten; we are only pure subject of knowledge; we are only that one eye of the world which looks out from all knowing creatures, but which can become perfectly free from the service of will in man alone. Thus all difference of individuality so entirely disappears, that it is all the same whether the perceiving eye belongs to a mighty king or to a wretched beggar; for neither joy nor complaining can pass that boundary with us.” [1909/ 1818/19, Vol I: 262].
Derek Parfit’s most famous passage from Reasons and Persons concerns the feeling of liberation he received from realising that there is not really any such thing as a persistent Self, the moral virtue it helped him acquire, and the reduction in his fear of death it brought about:
“When I believed that my existence was such a further fact, I seemed imprisoned in myself. My life seemed like a glass tunnel, through which I was moving faster every year, and at the end of which there was darkness. When I changed my view, the walls of my glass tunnel disappeared. I now live in the open air. There is still a difference between my life and the lives of other people. But the difference is less. Other people are closer. I am less concerned about the rest of my own life, and more concerned about the lives of others.
When I believed the Non-Reductionist View, I also cared more about my inevitable death.  After my death, there will be no one living who will be me. I can now redescribe this fact.  […] My death will break the more direct relations between my present experiences and future experiences, but it will not break various other relations.  This is all there is to the fact that there will be no one living who will be me.  Now that I have seen this, my death seems to me less bad.” [1984: 281].

In summary, I think Hume was right: there are no persistent individuals, and there is no spooky Self which somehow preserves numerical identity between different human time slices. From this, it follows, as Hume saw, that conflicts over accounts of personal identity are essentially conflicts over what people think matters. From this basis, in turn, one can see that it may be morally and emotionally good for many people to try to weaken their endurantist intuitions.









Reference List

Hume, David (1737). A Treatise of Human Nature, 1992 edition, Prometheus Books, New York.
Lewis, David (1971). “Counterparts of persons and their bodies”, Journal of Philosophy, 68 (7): 203-211.

Nichols, Shaun & Bruno, Michael (2010). “Intuitions about personal identity: An empirical study”, Philosophical Psychology, 23 (3): 293-312.

Parfit, Derek (1984). Reasons and Persons, Clarendon Press, Oxford.

Schopenhauer, Arthur (1909/ 1818/19). Die Welt als Wille und Vorstellung, trans. R.B. Haldane and J. Kemp. Kegan Paul, Trench, Trübner & Co, London.

Wiggins, David (1980). Sameness and Substance, Basil Blackwell, Oxford.

Uncited:

Gallois, Andre, "Identity Over Time", The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Winter 2016 Edition), Edward N. Zalta (ed.), URL = <https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2016/entries/identity-time/>.

Noonan, Harold and Curtis, Ben, "Identity", The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Spring 2017 Edition), Edward N. Zalta (ed.), URL = <https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2017/entries/identity/>.

Hawley, Katherine, "Temporal Parts", The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Winter 2015 Edition), Edward N. Zalta (ed.), URL = <https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2015/entries/temporal-parts/>.





[1] And what is this “I”? This human instance-instant (instance-instant of the kind “human”) doesn’t know. Every time the human-instance instant (or human ‘time slice’) typing the words uses the first-person pronoun in this essay he (the instance-instant with male sex) means “the human instance-instant typing the words”.
[2] Not being an ontological Quinean, in the sense of believing in the project of trying to construct a ‘flat’ ontology (or literally any other Quinean doctrine), I more mean to say that particulars which persist numerically through time, if we want to say they exist because it’s convenient, are clearly less fundamental – dependent on the instant-instances – and are also ontologically posterior to the abstract sorts (it seems to me that I’m basically forced to the latter view by adopting the former, though I won’t elaborate on that point because I don’t have space).
[3] I’ll later make an argument for this. The high modality is explained by the fact that I think this is obviously true. I should probably temper these sentiments in light of concerns about disagreement of epistemic peers.
[4] This may be too harsh… Probably: I’m only 20.

No comments:

Post a Comment